Aristotle's
Aristotle devotes great attention to the
nature, structure and basic elements of the ideal tragic plot. Tragedy is the
depiction of action consisting of incidents and events. Plot is the arrangement
of these incident and events. It contains the kernel of the action. Aristotle
says that plot is the first principle, the soul of tragedy. He lists six
formative elements of a tragedy – Plot, character, thought, melody, diction,
spectacle and gives the first place to plot.
The Greek word for 'poet' means a 'maker',
and the poet is a 'maker', not because he makes verses but he makes plots.
Aristotle differentiates between 'story' and 'plot'. The poet need not make his
story. Stories from history, mythology, or legend are to be preferred, for they
are familiar and understandable. Having chosen or invented the story, it must
be put to artistic selection and order. The incidents chosen must be 'serious',
and not 'trivial', as tragedy is an imitation of a serious action that arouse
pity and fear.
Aristotle says that the tragic plot must be a
complete whole. It must have a beginning, a middle and an end. It must have a
beginning, i.e. it must not flow out of some prior situation. The beginning
must be clear and intelligible. It must not provoke to ask 'why' and 'how'. A
middle is consequent upon a situation gone before. The middle is followed
logically by the end. And end is consequent upon a given situation, but is not
followed by any further incident. Thus artistic wholeness implies logical
link-up of the various incidents, events and situations that form the plot.
The plot must have a certain magnitude or
'length'. 'Magnitude' here means 'size'. It should be neither too small nor too
large. It should be long enough to allow the process of change from happiness
to misery but not too long to be forgotten before the end. If it is too small,
its different parts will not be clearly distinguishable from each other.
Magnitude also implies order and proportion and they depend upon the magnitude.
The different parts must be properly related to each other and to the whole.
Thus magnitude implies that the plot must have order, logic symmetry and
perspicuity.
Aristotle considers the tragic plot to be an
organic whole, and also having organic unity in its action. An action is a
change from happiness to misery or vice versa and tragedy must depict one such
action. The incidents impart variety and unity results by arranging the
incidents so that they all tend to the same catastrophe. There might be
episodes for they impart variety and lengthen the plot but they must be
properly combined with the main action following each other inevitably. It must
not be possible to remove or to invert them without injuring the plot.
Otherwise, episodic plots are the worst of all.
'Organc unity' cannot be provided only by the
presence of the tragic hero, for many incidents in hero's life cannot be
brought into relation with the rest. So there should be proper shifting and
ordering of material.
Aristotle joins organic unity of plot with
probability and necessity. The plot is not tied to what has actually happened
but it deals with what may probably or necessarily happen. Probability and
necessity imply that there should be no unrelated events and incidents. Words
and actions must be in character. Thus probability and necessity imply unity
and order and are vital for artistic unity and wholeness.
'Probability' implies that the tragic action
must be convincing. If the poet deals with something improbable, he must make
it convincing and credible. He dramatist must procure, "willing suspension
of disbelief". Thus a convincing impossibility is to be preferred to an
unconvincing possibility.
Aristotle rules out plurality of action. He
emphasizes the Unity of Action but has little to say about the Unity of Time
and the Unity of Place. About the Unity of Time he merely says that tragedy
should confine itself to a single revolution of the sun. As regards the Unity
of Place, Aristotle said that epic can narrate a number of actions going on all
together in different parts, while in a drama simultaneous actions cannot be
represented, for the stage is one part and not several parts or places.
Tragedy is an imitation of a 'serious action'
which arouses pity and fear. 'Serious' means important, weighty. The plot of a
tragedy essentially deals with great moral issues. Tragedy is a tale of
suffering with an unhappy ending. This means that the plot of a tragedy must be
a fatal one. Aristotle rules out fortunate plots for tragedy, for such plot
does not arouse tragic emotions. A tragic plot must show the hero passing from
happiness to misery and not from misery to happiness. The suffering of the hero
may be caused by an enemy or a stranger but it would be most piteous when it is
by chance caused by friends and relatives who are his well-wishers.
According to Aristotle, Tragic plots may be
of three kinds, (a) Simple, (b) Complex and (c) Plots based on or depicting
incidents of suffering. A Simple plot is without any Peripety and Anagnorisis
but the action moves forward uniformly without any violent or sudden change.
Aristotle prefers Complex plots. It must have Peripeteia, i.e. "reversal
of intention" and Anagnorisis, i.e. "recognition of truth".
While Peripeteia is ignorance of truth, Anagnorisis is the insight of truth
forced upon the hero by some signs or chance or by the logic events. In ideal
plot Anagnorisis follows or coincides with Peripeteia.
'Recognition' in the sense is closely akin to
reversal. Recognition and reversal can be caused by separate incidents. Often
it is difficult to separate the two. Complex plots are the best, for
recognition and reversal add the element of surprise and "the pitiable and
fearful incidents are made more so by the shock of surprise".
As regards the third kind of plot, Aristotle
rates it very low. It derives its effect from the depiction of torture, murder,
maiming, death etc. and tragic effect must be created naturally and not with
artificial and theatrical aids. Such plots indicate a deficiency in the art of
the poet.
In making plots, the poets should make their
denouements, effective and successful. Unraveling of the plot should be done
naturally and logically, and not by arbitrary devices, like chance or
supernatural devices. Aristotle does not consider Poetic Justice necessary for
Tragedy. He rules out plots with a double end i.e. plots in which there is
happiness for one, and misery for others. Such plots weaken the tragic effect.
It is more proper to Comedy. Thus Aristotle is against Tragi-comedy.
__________________________________________________________________________
Aristotle's Concept of Catharsis
Aristotle writes that the function of tragedy
is to arouse the emotions of pity and fear, and to affect the Katharsis of
these emotions. Aristotle has used the term Katharsis only once, but no phrase
has been handled so frequently by critics, and poets. Aristotle has not
explained what exactly he meant by the word, nor do we get any help from the
Poetics. For this reason, help and guidance has to be taken from his other
works. Further, Katharsis has three meaning. It means 'purgation',
'purification', and 'clarification', and each critic has used the word in one
or the other senses. All agree that Tragedy arouses fear and pity, but there
are sharp differences as to the process, the way by which the rousing of these
emotions gives pleasure.
Katharsis has been taken as a medical
metaphor, 'purgation', denoting a pathological effect on the soul similar to
the effect of medicine on the body. This view is borne out by a passage in the
Politics where Aristotle refers to religious frenzy being cured by certain
tunes which excite religious frenzy. In Tragedy:
…pity and fear, artificially stirred the
latent pity and fear which we bring with us from real life.
In the Neo-Classical era, Catharsis was taken
to be an allopathic treatment with the unlike curing unlike. The arousing of
pity and fear was supposed to bring about the purgation or 'evacuation' of
other emotions, like anger, pride etc. As Thomas Taylor holds:
We learn from the terrible fates of evil men
to avoid the vices they manifest.
F. L. Lucas rejects the idea that Katharsis
is a medical metaphor, and says that:
The theatre is not a hospital.
Both Lucas and Herbert Reed regard it as a
kind of safety valve. Pity and fear are aroused, we give free play to these
emotions which is followed by emotional relief. I. A. Richards' approach to the
process is also psychological. Fear is the impulse to withdraw and pity is the
impulse to approach. Both these impulses are harmonized and blended in tragedy
and this balance brings relief and repose.
The ethical interpretation is that the tragic
process is a kind of lustration of the soul, an inner illumination resulting in
a more balanced attitude to life and its suffering. Thus John Gassner says that
a clear understanding of what was involved in the struggle, of cause and
effect, a judgment on what we have witnessed, can result in a state of mental
equilibrium and rest, and can ensure complete aesthetic pleasure. Tragedy makes
us realize that divine law operates in the universe, shaping everything for the
best.
During the Renaissance, another set of
critics suggested that Tragedy helped to harden or 'temper' the emotions.
Spectators are hardened to the pitiable and fearful events of life by
witnessing them in tragedies.
Humphrey House rejects the idea of
'purgation' and forcefully advocates the 'purification' theory which involves
moral instruction and learning. It is a kind of 'moral conditioning'. He points
out that, 'purgation means cleansing'.
According to 'the purification' theory,
Katharsis implies that our emotions are purified of excess and defect, are
reduced to intermediate state, trained and directed towards the right objects
at the right time. The spectator learns the proper use of pity, fear and
similar emotions by witnessing tragedy. Butcher writes:
The tragic Katharsis involves not only the
idea of emotional relief, but the further idea of purifying the emotions so
relieved.
The basic defect of 'purgation' theory and
'purification' theory is that they are too much occupied with the psychology of
the audience. Aristotle was writing a treatise not on psychology but on the art
of poetry. He relates 'Catharsis' not to the emotions of the spectators but to
the incidents which form the plot of the tragedy. And the result is the
"clarification" theory.
The paradox of pleasure being aroused by the
ugly and the repellent is also the paradox involved in tragedy. Tragic
incidents are pitiable and fearful.
They include horrible events as a man
blinding himself, a wife murdering her husband or a mother slaying her children
and instead of repelling us produce pleasure. Aristotle clearly tells us that
we should not seek for every pleasure from tragedy, "but only the pleasure
proper to it". 'Catharsis' refers to the tragic variety of pleasure. The
Catharsis clause is thus a definition of the function of tragedy, and not of
its emotional effects on the audience.
Imitation does not produce pleasure in
general, but only the pleasure that comes from learning, and so also the
peculiar pleasure of tragedy. Learning comes from discovering the relation
between the action and the universal elements embodied in it. The poet might
take his material from history or tradition, but he selects and orders it in
terms of probability and necessity, and represents what, "might be".
He rises from the particular to the general and so is more universal and more
philosophical. The events are presented free of chance and accidents which
obscure their real meaning. Tragedy enhances understanding and leaves the
spectator 'face to face with the universal law'.
Thus according to this interpretation,
'Catharsis' means clarification of the essential and universal significance of
the incidents depicted, leading to an enhanced understanding of the universal
law which governs human life and destiny, and such an understating leads to
pleasure of tragedy. In this view, Catharsis is neither a medical, nor a
religious or moral term, but an intellectual term. The term refers to the
incidents depicted in the tragedy and the way in which the poet reveals their
universal significance.
The clarification theory has many merits.
Firstly, it is a technique of the tragedy and not to the psychology of the
audience. Secondly, the theory is based on what Aristotle says in the Poetics,
and needs no help and support of what Aristotle has said in Politics and
Ethics. Thirdly, it relates Catharsis both to the theory of imitation and to
the discussion of probability and necessity. Fourthly, the theory is perfectly
in accord with current aesthetic theories.
According to Aristotle the basic tragic
emotions are pity and fear and are painful. If tragedy is to give pleasure, the
pity and fear must somehow be eliminated. Fear is aroused when we see someone
suffering and think that similar fate might befall us. Pity is a feeling of
pain caused by the sight of underserved suffering of others. The spectator sees
that it is the tragic error or Hamartia of the hero which results in suffering
and so he learns something about the universal relation between character and
destiny.
To conclude, Arstotle's conception of
Catharsis is mainly intellectual. It is neither didactic nor theoretical,
though it may have a residual theological element. Aristotle's Catharsis is not
a moral doctrine requiring the tragic poet to show that bad men come to bad
ends, nor a kind of theological relief arising from discovery that God's laws
operate invisibly to make all things work out for the best.
_____________________________________
Aristotle's Theory of Imitation
Aristotle did not invent the term
"imitation". Plato was the first to use the word in relation with
poetry, but Aristotle breathed into it a new definite meaning. So poetic
imitation is no longer considered mimicry, but is regarded as an act of
imaginative creation by which the poet, drawing his material from the
phenomenal world, makes something new out of it.
In Aristotle's view, principle of imitation
unites poetry with other fine arts and is the common basis of all the fine
arts. It thus differentiates the fine arts from the other category of arts.
While Plato equated poetry with painting, Aristotle equates it with music. It
is no longer a servile depiction of the appearance of things, but it becomes a
representation of the passions and emotions of men which are also imitated by
music. Thus Aristotle by his theory enlarged the scope of imitation. The poet
imitates not the surface of things but the reality embedded within. In the very
first chapter of the Poetic, Aristotle says:
Epic poetry and Tragedy, Comedy also and
Dithyrambic poetry, as also the music of the flute and the lyre in most of
their forms, are in their general conception modes of imitation. They differ
however, from one another in three respects – their medium, the objects and the
manner or mode of imitation, being in each case distinct.
The medium of the poet and the painter are different.
One imitates through form and colour, and the other through language, rhythm
and harmony. The musician imitates through rhythm and harmony. Thus, poetry is
more akin to music. Further, the manner of a poet may be purely narrative, as
in the Epic, or depiction through action, as in drama. Even dramatic poetry is
differentiated into tragedy and comedy accordingly as it imitates man as better
or worse.
Aristotle says that the objects of poetic
imitation are "men in action". The poet represents men as worse than
they are. He can represent men better than in real life based on material
supplied by history and legend rather than by any living figure. The poet
selects and orders his material and recreates reality. He brings order out of
Chaos. The irrational or accidental is removed and attention is focused on the
lasting and the significant. Thus he gives a truth of an ideal kind. His mind
is not tied to reality:
It is not the function of the poet to relate
what has happened but what may happen – according to the laws of probability or
necessity.
History tells us what actually happened;
poetry what may happen. Poetry tends to express the universal, history the
particular. In this way, he exhibits the superiority of poetry over history.
The poet freed from the tyranny of facts, takes a larger or general view of
things, represents the universal in the particular and so shares the
philosopher's quest for ultimate truth. He thus equates poetry with philosophy
and shows that both are means to a higher truth. By the word 'universal'
Aristotle signifies:
How a person of a certain nature or type
will, on a particular occasion, speak or act, according to the law of
probability or necessity.
The poet constantly rises from the particular
to the general. He studies the particular and devises principles of general
application. He exceeds the limits of life without violating the essential laws
of human nature.
Elsewhere Aristotle says, "Art imitates
Nature". By 'Nature' he does not mean the outer world of created things
but "the creative force, the productive principle of the universe."
Art reproduce mainly an inward process, a physical energy working outwards,
deeds, incidents, situation, being included under it so far as these spring
from an inward, act of will, or draw some activity of thought or feeling. He
renders men, "as they ought to be".
The poet imitates the creative process of
nature, but the objects are "men in action". Now the 'action' may be
'external' or 'internal'. It may be the action within the soul caused by all
that befalls a man. Thus, he brings human experiences, emotions and passions
within the scope of poetic imitation. According to Aristotle's theory, moral
qualities, characteristics, the permanent temper of the mind, the temporary
emotions and feelings, are all action and so objects of poetic imitation.
Poetry may imitate men as better or worse
than they are in real life or imitate as they really are. Tragedy and epic
represent men on a heroic scale, better than they are, and comedy represents
men of a lower type, worse than they are. Aristotle does not discuss the third
possibility. It means that poetry does not aim at photographic realism. In this
connection R. A. Scott-James points out that:
Aristotle knew nothing of the
"realistic" or "fleshy" school of fiction – the school of
Zola or of Gissing.
Abercrombie, in contrast, defends Aristotle
for not discussing the third variant. He says:
It is just possible to imagine life exactly
as it is, but the exciting thing is to imagine life as it might be, and it is
then that imagination becomes an impulse capable of inspiring poetry.
Aristotle by his theory of imitation answers
the charge of Plato that poetry is an imitation of "shadow of
shadows", thrice removed from truth, and that the poet beguiles us with
lies. Plato condemned poetry that in the very nature of things poets have no
idea of truth. The phenomenal world is not the reality but a copy of the
reality in the mind of the Supreme. The poet imitates the objects and phenomena
of the world, which are shadowy and unreal. Poetry is, therefore, "the
mother of lies".
Aristotle, on the contrary, tells us that art
imitates not the mere shows of things, but the 'ideal reality' embodied in very
object of the world. The process of nature is a 'creative process'; everywhere
in 'nature there is a ceaseless and upward progress' in everything, and the
poet imitates this upward movement of nature. Art reproduces the original not
as it is, but as it appears to the senses. Art moves in a world of images, and
reproduces the external, according to the idea or image in his mind. Thus the
poet does not copy the external world, but creates according to his 'idea' of
it. Thus even an ugly object well-imitated becomes a source of pleasure. We are
told in "The Poetics":
Objects which in themselves we view with
pain, we delight to contemplate when reproduced with minute fidelity; such as
the forms of the most ignoble animals and dead bodies.
The real and the ideal from Aristotle's point
of view are not opposites; the ideal is the real, shorn of chance and accident,
a purified form of reality. And it is this higher 'reality' which is the object
of poetic imitation. Idealization is achieved by divesting the real of all that
is accidental, transient and particular. Poetry thus imitates the ideal and the
universal; it is an "idealized representation of character, emotion,
action – under forms manifest in sense." Poetic truth, therefore, is
higher than historical truth. Poetry is more philosophical, more conducive to
understanding than Philosophy itself.
Thus Aristotle successfully and finally
refuted the charge of Plato and provided a defence of poetry which has ever
since been used by lovers of poetry in justification of their Muse. He breathed
new life and soul into the concept of poetic imitation and showed that it is,
in reality, a creative process
_________________________________________________
Aristotle's concept of ideal tragic hero:
Hamartia
No passage in "The Poetics" with
the exception of the Catharsis phrase has attracted so much critical attention
as his ideal of the tragic hero.
The function of a tragedy is to arouse the
emotions of pity and fear and Aristotle deduces the qualities of his hero from
this function. He should be good, but not perfect, for the fall of a perfect
man from happiness into misery, would be unfair and repellent and will not
arouse pity. Similarly, an utterly wicked person passing from happiness to
misery may satisfy our moral sense, but will lack proper tragic qualities. His
fall will be well-deserved and according to 'justice'. It excites neither pity
nor fear. Thus entirely good and utterly wicked persons are not suitable to be
tragic heroes.
Similarly, according to Aristotelian law, a
saint would be unsuitable as a tragic hero. He is on the side of the moral
order and hence his fall shocks and repels. Besides, his martyrdom is a
spiritual victory which drowns the feeling of pity. Drama, on the other hand,
requires for its effectiveness a militant and combative hero. It would be
important to remember that Aristotle's conclusions are based on the Greek drama
and he is lying down the qualifications of an ideal tragic hero. He is here
discussing what is the very best and not what is good. Overall, his views are
justified, for it requires the genius of a Shakespeare to arouse sympathy for
an utter villain, and saints as successful tragic heroes have been extremely
rare.
Having rejected perfection as well as utter
depravity and villainy, Aristotle points out that:
"The ideal tragic hero … must be an
intermediate kind of person, a man not pre-eminently virtuous and just, whose
misfortune, however, is brought upon him not by vice or depravity but by some
error of judgment."
The ideal tragic hero is a man who stands
midway between the two extremes. He is not eminently good or just, though he
inclines to the side of goodness. He is like us, but raised above the ordinary
level by a deeper vein of feeling or heightened powers of intellect or will. He
is idealized, but still he has so much of common humanity as to enlist our
interest and sympathy.
The tragic hero is not evil or vicious, but
he is also not perfect and his disaster is brought upon him by his own fault.
The Greek word used here is "Hamartia" meaning "missing the
mark". He falls not because of the act of outside agency or evil but
because of Hamartia or "miscalculation" on his part. Hamartia is not
a moral failing and it is unfortunate that it was translated as "tragic
flaw" by Bradley. Aristotle himself distinguishes Hamartia from moral
failing. He means by it some error or judgment. He writes that the cause of the
hero's fall must lie "not in depravity, but in some error or Hamartia on
his part". He does not assert or deny anything about the connection of
Hamartia with hero's moral failings.
"It may be accompanied by moral
imperfection, but it is not itself a moral imperfection, and in the purest
tragic situation the suffering hero is not morally to blame."
Thus Hamartia is an error or miscalculation,
but the error may arise from any of the three ways: It may arise from
"ignorance of some fact or circumstance", or secondly, it may arise
from hasty or careless view of the special case, or thirdly, it may be an error
voluntary, but not deliberate, as acts committed in anger. Else and Martian
Ostwald interpret Hamartia and say that the hero has a tendency to err created
by lack of knowledge and he may commit a series of errors. This tendency to err
characterizes the hero from the beginning and at the crisis of the play it is
complemented by the recognition scene, which is a sudden change "from
ignorance to knowledge".
In fact, Hamartia is a word with various
shades of meaning and has been interpreted by different critics. Still, all
serious modern Aristotelian scholarship agreed that Hamartia is not moral
imperfection. It is an error of judgment, whether arising from ignorance of
some material circumstance or from rashness of temper or from some passion. It
may even be a character, for the hero may have a tendency to commit errors of
judgment and may commit series of errors. This last conclusion is borne out by
the play Oedipus Tyrannus to which Aristotle refers time and again and which
may be taken to be his ideal. In this play, hero's life is a chain or errors,
the most fatal of all being his marriage with his mother. If King Oedipus is
Aristotle's ideal hero, we can say with Butcher that:
"His conception of Hamartia includes all
the three meanings mentioned above, which in English cannot be covered by a
single term."
Hamartia is an error, or a series of errors,
"whether morally culpable or not," committed by an otherwise noble
person, and these errors derive him to his doom. The tragic irony lies in the
fact that hero may err mistakenly without any evil intention, yet he is doomed
no less than immorals who sin consciously. He has Hamartia and as a result his
very virtues hurry him to his ruin. Says Butcher:
"Othello in the modern drama, Oedipus in
the ancient, are the two most conspicuous examples of ruin wrought by
character, noble indeed, but not without defects, acting in the dark and, as it
seemed, for the best."
Aristotle lays down another qualification for
the tragic hero. He must be, "of the number of those in the enjoyment of
great reputation and prosperity". He must be a well-reputed individual
occupying a position of lofty eminence in society. This is so because Greed
tragedy, with which alone Aristotle was familiar, was written about a few
distinguished royal families. Aristotle considers eminence as essential for the
tragic hero. But Modern drama demonstrates that the meanest individual can also
serve as a tragic hero, and that tragedies of Sophoclean grandeur can be
enacted even in remote country solitudes.
However, Aristotle's dictum is quite
justified on the principle that, "higher the state, the greater the fall
that follows," or because heavens themselves blaze forth the death of
princes, while the death of a beggar passes unnoticed. But it should be
remembered that Aristotle nowhere says that the hero should be a king or at
least royally descended. They were the Renaissance critics who distorted
Aristotle and made the qualification more rigid and narrow.
No comments:
Post a Comment