Aristotle’s Poetics
1.
The Concept of Imitation
In The Poetics, Aristotle asserts that
literature is a function of human nature's instinct to imitate. This implies
that as humans, we are constantly driven to imitate, to create. By labeling
this creative impulse an "instinct," one is to believe that this
desire for imitation is a matter of survival, of necessity. The question then
arises, of what does one feel compelled to imitate and in what way does it aid
in our survival? According to essays by T.S. Eliot and Barbara Johnson, the
purpose of literature is to be a part of a necessary creative process,
sometimes to the extent that the creator is lost and consumed by the cause.
The first issue to tackle is the question of
what literature imitates. Imitation and representation encompass all the media
of artistic expression with the artist striving to represent aspects of reality
or human experience. This is done either through song, the visual arts, or
literature. The artist, in a sense, strives to imitate God by wielding creative
power and performing a human version of divine creation. The artist is
attempting to communicate his or her subjective interpretation of the world.
However, the use of an interpretive medium also poses a unique challenge. In
the case of Literature, imitation is complicated by the inherent limitations of
language. Despite, or perhaps because of these limitations, artist then becomes
part of a creative process in which the relationship between the writer, the
text, and the subject matter become intertwined, blurring distinction between
these separate components.
T.S. Eliot deals specifically with how one
should view literature in relation to its creator. He opposes the school of
literary criticism that judges a poem's effectiveness based on the history and
personality of the poet rather than the poem itself. According to Eliot, the
poet must understand his or her position in the literary tradition. He states
that "what is to be insisted upon is that the poet must develop or procure
the consciousness of the past and that he should continue to develop this
consciousness throughout his career"(CMS 407). According to Eliot the only
consciousness a writer should have is of his or her place in the literary
tradition. Consciousness of emotional authenticity is irrelevant for Eliot.
Consciousness of the literary past is what gives a text its individuality. The
individuality of the poet or the uniqueness of the emotions expressed in the
poem is unnecessary because, Eliot believes, "one error, in fact, of
eccentricity in poetry is to seek for new human emotions to express"(CMS
410). Eliot wants the focus to be on the actual text for its contribution to
the literary tradition rather than the poet's personality or emotional depth.
Questions of whether or not the poem realistically captures human experience
are not as important as whether the poem maintains its own emotional impact
regardless of the poet's history. Therefore, if one understands imitation as
the creator's representation of personal emotions or subjective experience,
Eliot does not see imitation as the goal of literature. The poem is not
representing something, but rather, it is existing on its own.
Despite the fact that Eliot does not see
"mimesis" or, imitation as the goal of poetry, his theory of
depersonalization of literature does relate to Aristotle's idea of mimesis.
Eliot does not view the poet's personal experience as the proper motivation for
good literature. During the creative process, the poet should experience
"a continual surrender of himself as he is at the moment to something
which is more valuable. The progress of an artist, is a continual
self-sacrifice, a continual extinction of personality" (CMS 407). However,
this does not mean that the poet does not communicate emotional depth through
poetry. A poet can still successfully capture certain epistemological and
philosophical truths about existence and reality. He or she is still fulfilling
the instinct to imitate. In fact, Elliot argues, only through depersonalization
can the poet successfully communicate his imitation because it is not bogged
down in subjective interpretation. Therefore, the poet is imitating and
representing, but Eliot believes it is possible only by escaping the self and
removing the personal implications of a text's meaning.
Barbara Johnson explores mimesis in relation
to the limitations of language in her essay, "A Hound, a Bay Horse, and a
Turtle Dove: Obscurity in Walden." Johnson focuses on Thoreau's use of
symbolic language and what she sees as his unintended goal. She understands
Thoreau's use of obscure symbols as representing an idea of obscurity rather
than actual objects or concepts. She asserts that "You are supposed to
recognize them as not as obscure symbols, but as symbols standing for the
obscure, the lost, the irretrievable"(CMS 658). In this sense, form
follows content. The symbols are purposely obscure because they represent the
irretrievable and obscure. Thoreau's imitation here is not relegated to a
particular experience of loss, but of a concept and he accomplishes this in an
intentionally cryptic fashion. This is because the concept he is attempting to
communicate is itself so unknowable, so he uses obscure terms.
Thoreau realizes the limitations of language.
He understood that the act of imitation is itself an endeavor limited by language.
Therefore, for Thoreau, this instinctual impulse toward imitation remains
exactly that an impulse toward
creativity despite the limitations of the medium. However, his text also
maintains a consciousness of its inherent limitations. Johnson calls Thoreau's
technique "catachreses," or, figurative substitutes for a literal
term that does not exist (CMS 659). Thoreau fulfills his imitative instinct by
using literature's representative, though inherently limited, faculty to
represent something, which can not be represented.
Johnson concludes her essay by stating that
Thoreau became so completely consumed in the creative act, that his figurative
language ceases to be understandable as either pure rhetoric or a literal
cataloguing of thoughts. She explains that, "what Thoreau has done in
moving to Walden Pond is to move himself, literally, into the world of his own
figurative language."(CMS 661) His writing loses its coherence because his
symbolism saturates and overwhelms the narrative. Johnson explains that
"Thoreau has literally crossed over into the very parable he is writing,
where reality itself has become a catachresis"(CMS 661). He has delved so
deeply into the act of representation that the reader is never sure of the
creator's true intent. Perhaps it is Thoreau's intent to illustrate that the
imitative power of literature is that one can never quite represent an idea,
thought, emotions, without disclaiming its true intent beforehand. The paradox
of artistic intent is that because of its inherent duality, art and literature
can never specifically be separated from its creator or its product.
Both Eliot and Johnson agree that a text
should posses a certain consciousness. For Eliot that consciousness is of the
literary tradition, of the text of human experience. As Johnson demonstrates
through Thoreau, text can not help but be conscious of its own limited
imitative capacity. Eliot believes that if a poet depersonalizes a text enough,
than it can really accomplish an expression of deep emotion or thought. Johnson
sees the medium of literature as an obstacle to actual representation, but that
ambiguity enhances the text to the extent that it "delights and
baffles" (CMS 655).
Aristotle's idea now takes on greater depth
given these new perspectives. He phrases it as an "instinct towards
imitation" because this impulse toward to creation is practically
unconscious. As thoughtful beings, humans are driven to pursue this creative
instinct. It is as innate an instinct for survival as the need for food and
shelter. Therefore we pursue this impulse toward imitation almost without
caring if we imitate successfully. We are acting within our given boundaries
and limitations. According to Johnson, that is what gives literature its
richness. Eliot believes the poet can transcend those limitations. Everyone
agrees that one must act on the creative instinct.
2.
Aristotle on Tragedy
The Nature of Tragedy: In the century after
Sophocles, the philosopher Aristotle analyzed tragedy. His definition: Tragedy
then, is an imitation of an action that is serious, complete, and of a certain
magnitude; in language embellished with each kind of artistic ornament, the
several kinds being found in separate parts of the play; in the form of action,
not of narrative; through pity and fear effecting the proper purgation of these
emotions.
Aristotle identified six basic elements: (1)
plot; (2) character; (3) diction (the choice of style, imagery, etc.); (4)
thought (the character's thoughts and the author's meaning); (5) spectacle (all
the visual effects; Aristotle considered this to be the least important
element); (6) song.
According to Aristotle, the central character
of a tragedy must not be so virtuous that instead of feeling pity or fear at
his or her downfall, we are simply outraged. Also the character cannot be so
evil that for the sake of justice we desire his or her misfortune. Instead,
best is someone"who is neither outstanding in virtue and righteousness;
nor is it through badness or villainy of his own that he falls into misfortune,
but rather through some flaw [hamartia]". The character should be famous
or prosperous, like Oedipus or Medea.
What Aristotle meant by hamartia cannot be
established. In each play we read you should particularly consider the
following possibilities. (1) A hamartia may be simply an intellectual mistake
or an error in judgement. For example when a character has the facts wrong or
doesn't know when to stop trying to get dangerous information. (2) Hamartia may
be a moral weakness, especially hubris, as when a character is moral in every
way except for being prideful enough to insult a god. (Of course you are free
to decide that the tragic hero of any play, ancient or modern, does not have a
hamartia at all). The terms hamartia and hubris should become basic tools of
your critical apparatus.
The Concept of Tragedy: The word tragedy can
be applied to a genre of literature. It can mean 'any serious and dignified
drama that describes a conflict between the hero (protagonist) and a superior
force (destiny, chance, society, god) and reaches a sorrowful conclusion that
arouses pity or fear in the audience.' From this genre comes the concept of
tragedy, a concept which is based on the possibility that a person may be
destroyed precisely because of attempting to be good and is much better than
most people, but not perfect. (Irony, therefore, is essential and it is not
surprising that dramatic irony, which can so neatly emphasize irony, is common
in tragedies.) Tragedy implies a conflict between human goodness and reality.
Many scholars feel that if God rewards goodness either on earth or in heaven
there can be no tragedy. If in the end each person gets what he or she
deserves, tragedy is impossible. Tragedy assumes that this universe is rotten
or askew. Christians believe that God is good and just, hence, for certain
scholars tragedy is logically impossible. Of course a possible variation of the
tragic concept would allow a character to have a fault which leads to
consequences far more dire than he deserves. But tragic literature is not
intended to make people sad. It may arouse pity and fear for the suffering
protagonist, or for all humanity, especially ourselves. But usually it also is
intended to inspire admiration for the central character, and by analogy for all
mankind. In the tragic hero's fall there is the glory in his or her misfortune;
there is the joy which only virtue can supply. Floods, automobile accidents,
children's deaths, though terribly pathetic can never be tragic in the dramatic
sense because they do not occur as a result of an individual man's grandeur and
virtue. After reading each book in the course, be sure you know whether it
presents a tragic view of life. (Incidentally, although some plays we read are
certainly tragic in all scholars' opinions, many Greek plays produced as
tragedies are not tragic by anyone's definition, including Aristotles'.)
Aristotle's Poetics: Basic Concepts You
should be aware of the following concepts and opinions of Aristotle's which
have tremendously influenced drama in the Western World.
a. Tragedies should not be episodic. That is,
the episodes in the plot must have a clearly probable or inevitable connection
with each other. This connection is best when it is believable but unexpected.
b. Complex plots are better than simple plots. Complex plots have recognitions
and reversals. A recognition is a change from ignorance to knowledge,
especially when the new knowledge identifies some unknown relative or dear one
whom the hero should cherish but was about to harm or has just harmed.
'Recognition' (anagnorisis) is now commonly applied to any self-knowledge the
hero gains as well as to insight to the whole nature or condition of mankind,
provided that that knowledge is associated, as Aristotle said it should be,
with the hero's 'reversal of fortune' (Greek: peripeteia). A reversal is a
change of a situation to its opposite. Consider Oedipus at the beginning and
end of Oedipus the King. Also consider in that play how a man comes to free
Oedipus of his fear about his mother, but actually does the opposite.
Recognitions are also supposed to be clearly connected with all the rest of the
action of the plot. c. Suffering (some fatal or painful action) is also to be
included in a tragic plot which, preferably, should end unhappily. d. The pity
and fear which a tragedy evokes, should come from the events, the action, not
from the mere sight of something on stage. e. Catharsis ('purification' or
'purgation') of pity and fear was a part of Aristotle's definition of tragedy.
The meaning of this phrase is extremely debatable. Among the many
interpretations possible, consider how well the following apply to our plays:
1) Purification of the audience's feelings of
pity and fear so that in real life we understand better whether we should feel
them. 2) Purgation of our pity and fear so that we can face life with less of
these emotions or more control over them. 3) Purification of the events of the
plot, so that the central character's errors or transgressions become
'cleansed' by his or her recognitions and suffering.
3.
Plot and Tragedy
In his Poetics [1] Aristotle (384-322 BC)
classifies plot into two types: simple [haplos], and complex [peplegmenos]. The
simple plot is defined as a unified construct of necessary and probable actions
accompanied by a change of fortune. The complex plot, says Aristotle, is
accompanied by two other features, namely; peripeteia or reversal, and
anagnorisis, or recognition. It is this which Aristotle feels is the best kind
of tragic plot, in that it provides the best possibility of delivering tragic
pleasure.
Before
we look at the distinctive features of the complex plot, it would perhaps be
instructive to examine those features which it shares with the simple plot. The
unity of structure recommended by Aristotle includes the tripartite division of
the plot into the beginning, the middle and the end, as well as the unities of
time and action. He stresses unified action, where all action in the plot
carries a definite link to other actions, and subsequent actions are the
necessary and probable outcomes of the former.
Necessary and probable are terms which recur
throughout the Poetics. They stand for the universality of poetry in that they
point to how or what actions should logically be in a given situation. Unity of
action, therefore, does not mean all that happens to the protagonist, but
precisely what comprises a particular whole action according to the norms of
necessity and probability. Unity of time, in contrast to its neo-classical
applications, here simply means the time span in which the tragic action can be
best comprehended by the audience, given the constraints of human memory, and
the wholeness of the action.
Finally, we come to the change of fortune. It
is either from good to bad or the reverse. The former is more characteristic of
tragedy but in a later section Aristotle complicates the idea by saying that
those plots where the catastrophe is averted by recognition are best. The
change of fortune is also accompanied by a complication of events [desis] and
their resolution [lusis].
Having
briefly examined the common aspects of both kinds of plot, we can now look at
the special attributes of the complex plot.
Let us take another look at Aristotle's
celebrated definition of complex action: 'A complex action is one where the
change is accompanied by such reversal or recognition or both.' Peripeteia has
been defined as a reversal of the action. If, however, it is just that, then
how is it different from the change of fortune? Clearly this is too limited a
definition of peripeteia and it would perhaps be pertinent to consider two
other definitions. Humphrey House [2] defines it as a 'reversal of intention'.
This definition takes into account the 'thought' or the dianoia exercised by
the character. House describes it as 'holding the wrong end of the stick'.
Peripeteia is therefore the turning of the stick thinking that it is the right
end. The ignorance behind any peripeteia is not mere ignorance. It is the
ignorance arising out of error. The other definition is more recent. Frank
Kermode [3] defines it as a 'disconfirmation followed by a consonance; the
interest of having our expectations falsified is obviously related to our wish
to reach discovery by an unexpected route. It has nothing to do with our
reluctance to get there at all. So that in assimilating the peripeteia we are
enacting that readjustment of our expectations in regard to an end'. This
points out the pleasure we receive from peripeteia which is quite different
from the straightforward following of a narrative to its end, or in other
words, mere change of fortune.
Having defined peripeteia and identified its
characteristic pleasure, we must also consider what this pleasure actually
consists of. This is the element of surprise or wonder [Gk. Thaumaston]. The
source of wonder is often the tragic recognition or anagnorisis. Recognition
has been variously defined. In Aristotle it is the recognition of persons through
tokens, artistic contrivances, memory, reasoning (including false inferences)
and lastly, arising out of the events themselves (as in Oedipus Rex). Aristotle
defines this anagnorisis as a change from ignorance to knowledge. In terms of
Humphrey House's analogy, it would mean the realization that you have got hold
of the wrong end of the stick. House himself defines recognition thus, 'The
discovery of the truth of the matter is the ghastly wakening from the state of
the ignorance which is the very essence of hamartia.' Other scholars define it
variously as 'a way in which the emotional potential . . . can be brought to
its highest voltage, so to speak at the moment of discharge', or, 'recognition
brings its illumination, which can shed retrospective light'.
Aristotle likes best the recognition which
arises out of the events themselves, as in Sophocles's Oedipus Rex. The whole
play is a step by step unravelling of Oedipus's true identity and Oedipus's
holding the wrong end of the stick, as it were, in trying to discover his
identity without knowing that the results will be catastrophic. At second best,
he places those tragedies where reasoning effects the recognition. Together
with these definitions, we could compare the slightly different angle from which
Terence Cave [4] views recognition. For him it is a stumbling block to belief
which disturbs the decorum. From this comparison we realize the complicated
nature of recognition. In the unravelling of the complex plot the point of the
recognition is very different from that possible in a simple plot. The
combination of peripeteia and recognition does not merely affect the characters
in the tragedy. They can also extend to the audience or the reader. The
unexpectedness of the tragic catastrophe which the complex plot brings [the
element of wonder or thaumaston] heightens our feelings of pity and fear as
well as other related emotions.
Here
it would be useful to look at another famous assertion of Aristotle's. In Ch
XIV of the Poetics he says, 'the pleasure which the poet should afford is that
which comes from pity and fear through imitation' [5]. Perhaps an examination
of pity and fear together with imitation can give us a better idea of the
pleasures incidental to tragedy. Let us start with an appraisal of pity and
fear. Pity and fear are man's sympathy for the good part of mankind in the bad
part of their experiences. Pity is evoked when there is a discrepancy between
the agent and Fate, and fear when there is a likeness between the agent and us.
Stephen Dedalus defines Pity and Fear in James Joyce's A Portrait of the Artist
as a Young Man. He calls pity the feeling which arrests the mind in the
presence of whatsoever is grave and constant in human-sufferings and unites it
with the human sufferer. Terror, or fear, is that which unites it with the
secret cause. [6].
Aristotle himself gives similar definitions
of these terms in his Rhetoric [books V and II]. There he defines them as a
species of pain. It is here that we can begin to consider the idea that tragic
pleasure derives from the purgation of these emotions. The idea of purgation as
a medical metaphor has been in vogue for a long time and can be substantiated
by examples from Aristotle's Problems [problem XXX] where coldness of black
bile accompanies 'despair and fear' and heat is the suggested cure which
restores the temperature to a temperate mean. Aristotle, unlike his teacher
Plato, says that the emotions are good in themselves. Therefore there should be
no need to purge the feelings of pity and fear. Instead, a more sensible
definition of tragic pleasure would be that concomitant with the proper feeling
of these emotions. By proper I mean a temperate attitude to these emotions as
Aristotle teaches in his Nichomachean Ethics. In Book II of his Ethics, he
says:
fear and confidence and appetite and anger
and pity and in general pleasure and pain may be felt both too much and too
little, and in both cases not well; but to feel them at the right times, with
reference to the right objects, towards the right people, with the right
motive, and in the right way, is what is both intermediate and best, and this
is characteristic of virtue. [7]
Aristotle's idea of the mean is derived from
the Pythagoreans who applied it to music. Here we may note that another place
where Aristotle uses the term catharsis is in his Politics and in the context
of giving 'relief to overcharged feeling' through music. Interestingly, here
too, he mentions pity and fear among the emotions dealt with and the
restoration is once again to a temperate mean. [8]
Is catharsis the only possible source of
pleasure in tragedy? Humphry House does not think so. Those who are temperate
in themselves and do not require an adjustment of their emotional reactions to
tragic situations, still derive pleasure from tragedy. Even Plato in The
Republic testifies to this fact: 'even the best of us enjoy it and let
ourselves be carried away by our feelings; and are full of praises for the
merits of the poet who can most powerfully affect us in this way.' [9]. The
pleasure arising out of poetry is therefore not entirely dependent on
catharsis. Instead, it works in two ways. In Book VII [section 11 - 14]
Aristotle discusses 'pure' pleasure and 'incidental' pleasure. The former is
universal and is accompanied by no pain and is likened to the pleasure arising
out of contemplation. Those who experience this do so solely by contemplating
and appraising the imitation of human emotions in tragedy.
It is through this view that we bring our
focus back on the last part of Aristotle's statement quoted above. Pleasure is
effected through imitation [or mimesis]. As Aristotle said [10] imitation is
itself a pleasurable act. All of this applies to epic as well as tragedy and
can probably be extended to other types of poetry. The specifically 'tragic'
pleasure is that pertaining to the medium and the dramatic mode of tragedy.
These constitute the specific imitative aspects of tragedy.
The idea of tragic pleasure therefore
necessarily consists as Aristotle aptly puts it 'in that which comes with pity
and fear through imitation'. A heightened sense of pity and fear is effected
when the necessary and probable events take an unexpected turn. This is
possible in the complex plot with the accompanying peripeteia and anagnorisis.
Thus our examination of the elements of the complex plot has led us to a
consideration of pity and fear. These together with imitation [or mimesis] help
us understand the pleasure peculiar to tragedy.
No comments:
Post a Comment